Biopolitics

Reading Roberto Esposito’s Bios has only confirmed my doubts about the whole discourse of what is today called “biopolitics.” Esposito’s book is a good one, in that it details, and clearly explains, what is meant by this term — but the effect of this has only been to strengthen my criticisms of the concept, or my sense of its inadequacy, when it comes to consider the role that “life,” or even just discourses about life, play in contemporary society.

Esposito traces both the ways that “life” — by which is meant the view of human beings as biological organisms, or the biological processes that human beings undergo, i.e. birth, growth, and death, sickness and health — has been caught up in politics (in the sense of being a subject, or object, of political practices, of political struggles, and of state power), and the ways that political theory has considered the meaning of “life.” This is a large field, as it includes, on the one hand, everything from medical interventions in the name of public health to Nazi practices of racial extermination; and on the other hand, philosophical concepts of the “body politic” and of the vitality of individuals, races, and peoples, in thought ever since the ancient Greeks, but especially in the span of time that extends from Hobbes, through Nietzsche, and on to 20th-century vitalism. This is a large amount of material to synthesize — and Esposito does it by tracing the lines in Western thought that lead towards and away from Nietzsche and Foucault, on the one hand, and the practices of the Nazi regime, on the other.

I’m not sure if the term “biopolitics” was invented by Foucault, but of course he did the most to make the concept thinkable. Foucault traces, in his genealogical investigations of medicine, madness, prisons, sexuality, etc., the ways that a regime of sovereignty, still prevalent in Europe in the Renaissance, was gradually displaced, or supplemented, by a regime of discipline, which was less concerned with the prohibition of certain behaviors than with the surveillance, manipulation, and management of all aspects of human life. Among other things, this involves a shift from being concerned with particular acts, and with clearly-defined hierarchies and chains of command, to being concerned with the bodies and souls of the entire populace. Foucault’s well-known account traces the links between attempts to contain disease by imposing quarantines, for instance, and attempts to regiment people in schools, factories, military barracks, and prisons. Power moves from prohibiting certain actions to actively shaping and manipulating peoples’ actions overall, and from drawing lines of exclusion, lines that it is forbidden to transgress, to finding ways to include everybody and everything within a grid of carefully managed alternatives and possibilities. Foucault also describes this as a shift from the power of death (the power of the sovereign to impose death as a punishment) to a right over life (the power of the state to manage, for the sake of health, growth, productivity, etc., all aspects of peoples’ bodily habits and tendencies). It is through this shift that “life” becomes a coherent concept, and a matter or focus of concern. “Life” gets defined conceptually, by doctors and judges as well as by philosophers, insofar as it emerges pragmatically as a target and focus of power. As always, Foucault is saying, not that “discourse” is the sole reality, but rather that both discourses and concrete, physical practices, varying historically, constitute so many ways in which we manage and control a “real” that always exceeds them. Contrary to some foolish interpretations, Foucault always remains a materialist, and a realist (in the ontological sense). “Life” refers to a particular way that we have conceived the multiplicity of lives, living beings, and life processes that surround and include us — but these always exist beyond our conceptualizations and manipulations of them.

So far so good. Esposito is an excellent close reader. He helpfully focuses on the ambiguity, in Foucault’s work: between claiming, on the one hand, that the regime of discipline and the management of life has replaced the earlier regime of sovereignty; and on the other hand, that such a disciplinary form of power is overlaid upon a sovereign power that continues to exist. Foucault proposes, precisely, that different modern regimes have been characterized by different mixtures between sovereign command over, and disciplinary positive investment of, the lives of individuals and populations. Esposito then moves backwards from Foucault to Nietzsche, in whom, he argues, “life” really emerges in its modern sense as an object and focus of both power and inquiry for the first time. For Nietzsche demystifies spirituality and the soul, presenting them as effects of physiology and neurology. Thus he allows us to understand all aspects of human culture and mentality as expressions of biological “life.” Further, there is a telling ambiguity in the way that Nietzsche regards “life” so constituted. On the one hand, there is a continual effort to judge, or evaluate, this “life” in terms of sickness and health, descent and ascent, decadence and triumph. In this respect, Nietzsche’s language is akin to that of the Social Darwinism of his time, and it clearly leads into the racist and fascist formulations of the following century. At the same time, Nietzsche affirms the mutability and metamorphosing power of “life”: in this sense, “sickness” is as vital as “health,” and is necessary in order to avoid stagnation; transgression and transformation are posed against the racist, pseudo-biological obsession (which reached its most terrifying expression in Nazism, but which was already prevalent among Nietzsche’s contemporaries) with “purity” and blood lines.

Again, Esposito’s reading is subtle, insightful, and overall unexceptionable. But at the same time, I found myself muttering, over and over again, a weary “so what?”. Whatever the historical value of reading Nietzsche, it is unclear to me that his texts have the same resonance, and the same importance, today in the 21st century that they did at the time of Nazism, or even that they did in France in the 1960s. Esposito refuses to extend his thought beyond the Nietzschean matrix, which he sees as dominating all that came since. Nietzshce remains the crucial reference point both for the “thanatopolitics” of Nazism, which he presents as the culmination of a certain kind of biopolitics, or politicization of “life” and death, and for the post-World War II emergence of a critical biopolitics, which Esposito sees exclusively as an attempt to rescue the forces of “life” from their subordination to the Nazi mythologies of the master race, of the centrality of childbirth, and of “the absolute normativization of life.” Heidegger, Arendt, Foucault, Simondon, Deleuze, 20th century French neo-Spinozianism: these are all read as efforts to liberate the forces of life from racial and familial normativization, from myths of purity and the Fatherland, etc. In this way, Esposito (much like Giorgio Agamben) sees the Holocaust as the central reference point for all biopolitical thought (and indeed, for all political thought whatsoever) today; with Niezsche providing the crucial conceptual framework, since his thought is the source both of 20th century notions of racial “cleanliness” and “health”, and of any possible critique and overcoming of such notions.

Can I dare to suggest (without being denounced as a “self-hating Jew”) that such a focus on the Holocaust, on the Adornian lament about the difficulty (or impossibility) of poetry (or anything else) “after Auschwitz,” is at this point, 63 years after the end of World War II, an obscurantist evasion rather than a moral imperative? Not only is Esposito’s focus upon Nazi thanatopolitics blindly Eurocentric, but it also fails to take account of the many forms racism, nationalist chauvinism, etc. have taken around the world in the last half century and more.The politicization of “life” and the management of “life” have become all the more pervasive and ubiquitous in the last half century, precisely because of (rather than in spite of) the discrediting (for the most part) of Nazi racist/nationalist themes. For instance, bigotry and genocide today tend to be expressed in “cultural” and religious terms, rather than in the terms the Nazis used; but these new terms are themselves related to how we have come to reconceptualize “life”. The same could be said about national and international responses to plagues (AIDS, SARS, bird flu), about population control measures (ranging all the way from the nativist encouragement of more births, and the attempts to ban all forms of birth control, to draconian attempts, like that of the Chinese government, to restrict population growth). And questions about agriculture and food production, about access to water and other vital resources, about the patenting of genetic material, about the use of biometric data to track both individuals and populations, and so on almost ad infinitum — all these are excluded from Esposito’s purview, largely because his reductively Eurocentric and Holocaust-centric view of the biologization of politics and the politicization of biology has no room for them.

More generally, the European (perhaps I should just say, Italian and French) view of biopolitics, which Esposito summarizes so well (and variants of which are upheld by Agamben, Negri, and others) ironically seems to ignore two things: biology, and political economy. It is telling that Esposito says nothing whatsoever about the ways in which biology and life have themselves been so totally reconfigured in the (more than) half-century following Watson and Crick’s determination of the structure of DNA. Biochemistry, genetics, neuroscience, genetic engineering, etc etc — all of these have profoundly changed how we conceive “life”, as well as how governments and corporations seek to manage and contain it — yet Esposito writes as if none of this were relevant. You wouldn’t know, from reading his genealogies, that today we tend to conceive a life force more on the model of mindless viral replication, than as anything like Bergson’s elan vital. Nor that eugenics has been recast, in its contemporary variant, as a matter of “bad genes” rather than “bad blood” (both formulations are lying, ideological ones, but they have entirely different connotations). Nor that the alleged fatality of genetic makeup has become an alibi for all sorts of social discrimination and inequality. Nor that the goal of contemporary biotechnology has to do with the pragmatic manipulation of genetic material — and hence with a certain notion of flexibility and differential control, rather than with the old-style racial essentialism. Although he is ostensibly concerned with how our society conceptualizes “life”, Esposito fails to consider how changes in biology have changed this conceptualization, and how things are still very much up for grabs today, as witnessed both by the continually emerging new potentials of biological research and bioltechnology, and by the ways in which, on a theoretical level, the orthodox neodarwinian synthesis is itself under considerable challenge from other biophilosophical visions (as I have written about before).

But not only is Esposito’s account of biology incomplete; his account of politics is, as well. This is due to the fact that, like far too many contemporary theorists, he considers questions of domination and authority, and political-philosophical arguments about the nature of law and sovereignty, without giving any thought to matters of political economy (more specifically, to processes of the extraction of surplus value, and the circulation and accumulation of capital). He has no account, in other words, of the ways in which conceptualizations of, and decisions about, “life”, are today at least as overdetermined by considerations of money and economy as they are by politics and political considerations. Biological research today is an expensive proposition; it must be publicly or privately funded (cf. the race between public and private bodies to sequence the human genome). Money sets the agenda. Even as the management of “life” expands, in terms of everything from health care to biometrics in the name of “public safety,” priorities are set more by cost-benefit analyses than by strictly “political” forms of decision. “Biopolitics” today is intimately entangled with neoliberalism, alike in theory, in policy, and in practice. And this is yet another dimension that Esposito altogether ignores. It’s significant that Foucault himself, in his lectures on The Birth of Biopolitics, presciently focused his analysis mostly on the strategies and doctrines of a then (1978-1979) just emerging neoliberalism. Foucault discusses both the post-War German state-guided version of neoliberalism, and (at lesser length, but even more crucially for an understanding of the world today) the neoliberalism of the Chicago School of Milton Friedman, and especially Gary Becker. Rather than offering any judgment on neoliberal practices, Foucault discusses them with the icy objectivity of an entomologist describing the habits of parasitic wasps. His emphasis, nonetheless, is on “the generalization of the grid of homo oeconomicus to domains that are not immediately and directly economic” (page 268). This expansion of the “economic” (as narrowly understood by neoclassical marginalism, as a form of calculative rationality) to all forms of human activity is indeed the largest “ideological” change we have experienced in the years since Foucault’s death; it has altered our very sense of the social and the political. It is odd that, even as Foucault, at the extreme limits of his own thought, proclaimed the fundamental significance of this transformation of the modern episteme, his supposed disciples almost completely ignore it. (And I should note that the crisis we are currently undergoing does not in the least represent the “end” of neoliberalism — the state’s rescue of financial institutions, and its efforts to reboot the economy through spending and re-regulation, come out of the same economistic principles that motivated the deregulation of the 1980s and 1990s in the first place).

I don’t have any conclusion to this discussion, except to say that a biopolitics that is relevant to, let alone adequate to, the contemporary world, and that at least tries (even if not altogether successfully) to be “as radical as reality itself,” is yet to be born. Certainly none of the currently fashionable European theorists and philosophers provide anything like it — or even a starting place.

15 thoughts on “Biopolitics”

  1. I really like this section:

    It is through this shift that “life” becomes a coherent concept, and a matter or focus of concern. “Life” gets defined conceptually, by doctors and judges as well as by philosophers, insofar as it emerges pragmatically as a target and focus of power. As always, Foucault is saying, not that “discourse” is the sole reality, but rather that both discourses and concrete, physical practices, varying historically, constitute so many ways in which we manage and control a “real” that always exceeds them. Contrary to some foolish interpretations, Foucault always remains a materialist, and a realist (in the ontological sense). “Life” refers to a particular way that we have conceived the multiplicity of lives, living beings, and life processes that surround and include us — but these always exist beyond our conceptualizations and manipulations of them.

    The feeling I got when reading Foucault’s lectures is that the causal relations of how constellations of power relations fix for a period of time the incorporeal materiality of life as a biopolitical reality (eg road safety stats, all matter of rates, etc) and intersections with the material of ‘stuff’ of life (biology, necessary environmental conditions to support life) were and are ambiguous. He talks about a governance of the event, of happenstance life-affecting blooms constitution of a population, but what about the evental character of these initiatives of governance? The causal relations themselves seem to be concretised opportunity.

    Also regarding your final point, Maurizio Lazzarato’s work certainly tries to reconcile a biopolitics with political economy. I wish I wasn’t an anglophone so I could read his Revolutions in Capital. Lastly, Nealon’s book on Foucault also engages with the notion of the economic in a similar fashion.

  2. Thanks for this post. I’ve just started delving into biopolitics and am relieved to read that you share my skepticism about the term. I glanced at Esposito; your overview persuades me that at this point I don’t need to go further into it. I always wonder why these biopolitics folks ignore slavery. I would think slavery crucial to a history of biopolitics in the US.

  3. Yeah, thanks for taking the time to write with such clarity on this.

    I’m really not up with the play, spectacularly so in fact, but what was wrong with Donna Haraway’s feminist and money-aware biopolitics? Always worked for me.

  4. One of the best blogposts I have read in a long, long time. You’ve condensed into a very short post exactly what I see as absolutely critical on a number of different fronts. I hope you don’t finally persuade Jodi or others like her that they needn’t “go further into it.” It seems to me that you are hoping a discussion of biopolitics adequate to the term, the realities of today, and Foucault’s initial task will soon be born. I’m all for it, and would love to be a part of such a rebirth.

    As it is, though, I can’t see getting around to beginning in earnest for another two to three projects, five to seven years at best. My wife and I have done a good amount of work up front both theoretically and in terms of investigating certain biological aspects of contemporary culture, but such a project is massive and she’s to write a dissertation in the next year, land a job, and, in all likelihood, write a second book toward tenure. She would really, really have to wind up in just the right place for this to work as a second book. Much more likely third or even fourth.

  5. hi Steve,

    Thanks for this. Don’t know when I’ll get to reading this book, but I plan to. One major disconnect for me with the biopolitics stuff is that it really easily can sound like the term is so general that it would apply to nearly any society at all. For instance, it seems to me that “the biological processes that human beings undergo, i.e. birth, growth, and death, sickness and health [have] been caught up in politics (in the sense of being a subject, or object, of political practices, of political struggles, and of state power)” for as long as politics existed. I mean, what could it mean to say that there was a political order that did not have life caught up in it? What would that look like?

    I find that ambiguity extra frustrating because the folk who use biopolitics as a term tend to talk about what are I think pretty important issues (including perhaps the odd epochal shift) at the same time that they address them clumsily.

    On Negri, who you mention in passing, I feel a bit self-conscious doing this, but I wrote a paper a few years ago criticizing Negri’s understanding of biopolitics, specifically as tied to his assertion that we are now in a new stage of capitalism defined by it being biopolitical. I’d do the paper differently if I wrote it nowadays but I think the basic point still stands.

    http://whatinthehell.blogsome.com/biopolitical-capitalism/

    take care,
    Nate

  6. True, power has been and is always about dominating life. What biopolitics achieves is the split and redefinition of the *body* – the traditional object of domination.

    This split results in the fragmentation of the individual and the dissolving of class consciousness.

    This split creates two dimensions, each of which excludes the traditional body: micro and macro.

    In classic political economy, technical revolutions force changes in creating value and drive class conflict. After WWII there were two technical revolutions that redefined the *body*.

    The first is the micro revolution, both in electronics and biology. These technologies transformed the site of exploitation from the productive to the consumptive sphere. When biotech created new ways to consider of physical existence through crops and drugs, and microprocessors changed our thinking from an analog sense of continuity to a digital form of yes/no – the locus of change shifts to consumption and the individual.

    The second is the macro revolution, where change crosses traditional national boundaries and can encompass the entire globe. At this level, consider environmental crises as a form of technology. As these technologies “advance” (in this case advancement results in destruction), population groups become *herds* – clusters of non-class conscious individuals whose immediate interests intersect with those in power.

    Note that with the micro case, the individual political actor has authority only with technical expertise. In the macro case, collective political actions are formed that cut across classes.

    As a result of these two technical revolutions, the individual body loses its privilege as a subject – the site of struggle – and its status changes into that of an object. Class consciousness was founded on the site of production as the location of exploitation. So as the body loses its position in struggle, class consciousness dissolves.

    The resultant multiplicity of political forms is a desperate search for the lost object – the body is gone and in its place is an implosion of political identity fragments: racial, gender, cultural.

    The importance of the Holocaust (and I would add the atomic bombing of Japan) was precisely that it signaled the end of the body (production) as the site of political struggle. Since WWII struggle and class have been separated – on the one hand via more individuation (cultural, psychological, identity, racial, sexual, genomic) and on the other supra-regional (environmental, resources, energy, migratory).

    This splitting off of class from struggle has been crucial to the rise of both globalization and neo-liberalism. Over the last 50 years we have seen the fall of the class struggle; perhaps we will be fortunate enough to witness again its rise.

  7. Thank you for this thoughtful post. As someone who has read a bit of Esposito, I must say, however, that I find your rejection of his work too quick and too total.

    First, you say that Esposito is blindly Eurocentric, yet his book opens by announcing its project with reference to examples of biopolitical questions taken not only from France, but also from Afghanistan, China, Russia, and Rwanda. In doing this, his point seems to be that thanatopolitics *cannot* be safely limited to Nazism, that the basic problematic of thanatopolitics *persists* and *survives* in the epoch of neoliberal and humanitarian globalization. His reading of Nazism (which, like his rereading of Nietzsche, is outlined in advance for him by his basic task: a retracing of Foucault’s path) seems designed to point out the *continuities* of Nazism with contemporary liberal societies. If your desire is to question the centrality of Nazism for biopolitical thinking, aren’t you then in heated *agreement* with Esposito? Don’t you both want to move away from Nazism as the exclusive or paradigmatic instance of biopolitics? If so, what’s the best way to do that? To focus on other examples of biopolitics, and to remain completely silent on Nazism? Or, like Arendt (on whom Esposito’s earlier books were written), to focus on the genealogical relationships between imperialism and slavery (in South Africa, in particular), Nazism, and the survival of Nazi thinking after the fall of Nazism? Why is it then, that in your comments on Eurocentrism, you remain silent on the opening pages of his book — the pages that frame his entire inquiry? If you took those seriously, wouldn’t you be able to generate another reading of Esposito’s project?

    Second, you criticize Esposito for leaving out the viral concept of life, but you don’t pursue the possibility that Esposito has already implicitly considered this concept when he claims that the concept of biopolitics only makes sense when it is linked to the immunitary paradigm (9 & ff.) Indeed, in the concluding his 2002 book _Immunitas_, Esposito does just this: he considers the problem of HIV/AIDS at length (and with reference to Haraway, Treichler, and imperial discourse), and more or less situates the question of viral life as the horizon for any and all philosophic thinking today. Not all immunitary dynamics are viral, but the viral problems you name — SARS, HIV/AIDS — pivot on immunitary dynamics, and are problematized by governments and activists alike in immunitary terms. A less dismissive reading of Esposito would mull that over: why is it that when life is politicized today, that politicization more often than not reduces to projects of immunization — to governmental interventions into (up to and including governmental abandonment of) the immune systems of individuals and populations? More importantly, why is it that with reference to the most important (or at least the most widespread of these immunitary questions, HIV/AIDS), the immunitary paradigm is failing or reaching its limits (i.e., that the great colonial invention of inoculation and vaccination is, w/r/t HIV, and despite great expenditures, impotent — and this, btw, is one answer to your ‘so what’)? In short, why are you silent about Esposito’s central argument, namely, that biopolitics is only coherent with reference to the problem of immunity — that the immunitary paradigm is the blindspot of Foucault’s concept of biopolitics?

    It’s easy to point out “exclusions” from any given text (because all texts leave out more than they include). The difficult thing is to read a text on its own terms — immanent critique — and to point out its exclusions from within. On these terms, I think, the jury on Esposito is still out.

  8. Two different starting points (that incorporate political economy): “Biocapital: the Constitution of Postgenomic Life” by Sunder Rajan Kaushik; “Dolly Mixtures: the Remaking of Genealogy” by Sarah Franklin. Time will tell?

  9. If you find the time to have a look at “In Search of the Origins of Nazi Monstrosity” you will find some hard facts followed by a tentative explanation. (Published by Dorrance Publishing Co.) What is your view on the Austro-Bavarian origin of the annihilation process?

    Jean Haussmann

Leave a Reply

Your email address will not be published. Required fields are marked *

This site uses Akismet to reduce spam. Learn how your comment data is processed.